-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
section_21.tex
167 lines (126 loc) · 15.1 KB
/
section_21.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% section.tex %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
%
% sample section
%
% Use this file as a template for your own input.
%
%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%% Springer-Verlag %%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%%
%\motto{Use the template \emph{section.tex} to style the various elements of your section content.}
\subsection{Finally: A New Beginning}
%\sectionmark{Starting Again}
\label{starting_pw} % Always give a unique label
% use \sectionmark{}
% to alter or adjust the section heading in the running head
%\sectionmark{Some Introductions}
One can imagine the collective sighs of all those read through the previous section to get to this, the \emph{exciting} part of the module, almost deafening. Here we will first start our proper discussion of the \pwt (and how we told a \emph{bit} of a fib earlier about the specific formulation we prove), along with some bits and bobs as to how we will prove it, and some previews of what it entails. There are two broad parts to the proof we will discuss -- although each is deserving of a chapter (or perhaps even more) on its own, and so their perhaps a bit more rushed than deserved proofs are outsourced to a section of their own each. For now, we start by dipping our toes into what we've been building to throughout the last entire first part.
\bigskip
\centerline{\rule{0.3333\linewidth}{.2pt}}
\smallskip
\subsection{How We're Going to Prove It}
As mentioned before -- but bears repeating -- our approach to proving \pwt (in our special little case) broadly follows that of Bhardwaj, and van den Dries \cite{bhardwaj_pilawilkie_2022}; a recent paper that only came out this year (should you be reading this in 2022). Their major contribution includes using \sacds to simplify several arguments of the original proof by Pila and Wilkie. They also provide a full treatment of a recent variant \cite{binyamini_yomdingromov_2021} of the (classical) Yomdin-Gromov theorem \cite{gromov_entropy_1987} (again, assuming your readership takes places not too soon after these words reach the page) in 2021, as well as a result of Bombieri and Pila \cite{bombieri_number_1989}, which is also made use of. In our case, we are going to be following the (recent) treatment of what we will come to colloquially call \emph{parameterization} by \cite{binyamini_yomdingromov_2021}.
%\centerline{\rule{0.6665\linewidth}{.2pt}}
%\footnote{Please note that this horizontal line is \emph{not} intended to cause any calming effects, as we have used a \textit{similar} (but distinct) line for previously. Delineation is all we intend this to be used for, and it is all that the reader is permitted to take from it. Observe with caution and most importantly, integrity.}
%\bigskip
\subsubsection{Some Recollections and Definitions}
Let us now begin with a recollection of our setting. We are no longer going to speak to the generality of any ordered field, and instead, an \om expansion $\Rtildefull$ of the ordered field of $\overline{\R}$. Ultimately, the \pwt is about rational points on definable sets -- so taking definable sets over this expansion (supposing points have $n$ dimensions) and intersecting with $\Q^n$, then \pw tells us something about the number of such points we can expect; in short, how \emph{few} of them we should expect up to a certain \emph{height}. This concept was briefly touched upon early in the first part. Still, to recap, we can define certain functions that characterize the height of a number (\`a la multiplicative height for rationals) and then bound the size of this set from above as a function of that height parameter. Without the use of a height, there could, of course, be infinitely-many points, so this concept is crucial (and broadly the \emph{point} of the theorem).
Let's begin by again defining the multiplicative height on $\Q$.
\begin{definition}[Multiplicative Height on $\Q$]
Suppose some $q = \sfrac{a}{b}$ for $a, b$ coprime, $a, b \in \Z$, and $b \neq 0$. Then, the height function is denoted by $\funcdom{H}{\Q}{\Zgeq{0}}$, and defined
\begin{align*}
H(q) = \max{ \left\{ \ \norm{a}, \ \norm{b} \ \right\} }
\end{align*}
for $\norm{\cdot}$ simply the absolute value on $\Q$.
\label{defn:Q_height}
\end{definition}
\subsubsection{A Little Idiosyncrasy}
\begin{svgraybox}
For reasons of preserving syntax used consistently (rather than some off-handed syntax we have been replacing) throughout this part of the course, we overload the use of $H$ as both a function on the rational numbers (and later just any height function) that maps some $q \in \Q^n$ to its height, \emph{as well as} the integral height bound or value itself. You will often find sentences of the form `fixing some $H \geq 1$, we take $X(S, H)$ to be the set $\{ s \in S \ \colon \ H(s) \leq H \}$'. While a bit confusing, especially at first blush, this choice for syntactic overloading was made due to its persistence throughout Dr. Jones' lectures.
\end{svgraybox}
\begin{corollary}
Fixing some height, $H$, there are only finitely many $q \in \Q$ with height $H$.
\end{corollary}
\begin{proof}
This should be clear.
\end{proof}
As usual, we now address the multidimensional-case
\begin{definition}[Multiplicative Height on $\Q^n$]
Suppose some $q = (\vonevm{q}{n}) \in \Q^n$ for $n \in \N$, all in lowest terms as before, then we define the height function to be the coordinate-wise maximum:
\begin{align*}
H(q) = \max{ \left\{ \ H(q_j) \colon 1 \leq j \leq n \ \right\} }.
\end{align*}
\label{defn:Qn_height}
\end{definition}
With that in mind, we have the following definition.
\begin{definition}
Let $\XRn[X]{n}$ and $H \in \N$. Denote the set
\begin{align*}
\XQH[H] = \left\{ \ q \in X \cap \Q^n \ \colon H(q) \leq H \ \right\}
\end{align*}
and further, refer to the algebraic and transcendental parts of $X$ and their corresponding sets such that we have
\begin{align*}
\XQH[H] \setminus \XalgQH[H] = \XtrQH[H],
\end{align*}
where we trust the superscript notations to be clear.
\label{defn:height_sets}
\end{definition}
To rephrase what we said above, the \pwt gives us an upper bound on
\begin{align*}
\card{\XtrQH[H]},
\end{align*}
with $H$ as a parameter controlling the cardinality of this set. Ideally, we want good bounds on this, especially as $H \to \infty$ -- which quite nicely, \pw gives us.
\subsubsection{Building to \pw}
A special case of this coming from Pila (building on an earlier paper he had worked on with Bombieri) is the following:
\begin{theorem}[A Special Case by Pila]
Suppose $\funcdom{f}{[0, 1]}{\R}$ is analytic and transcendental, and further that $X = \graph{f}$. Then, for all $\eps > 0$, there exists some $c > 0$ such that for any $H \in \N$,
\begin{align*}
\card{\XQH[H]} \leq c \cdot H^{\eps}
\end{align*}
\end{theorem}
In general, a \defnb set may contain a rational line (with interior, that is), in which case the number of points is enormous. Here is where the idea of algebraic and transcendental parts of $X$, again denoted $\Xalg[x]$ and $\Xtr[X]$, becomes vital. However, we now do you the service of definition, such that anything useful can be done with them.
\begin{definition}[Algebraic Part of $X$]
The \emph{algebraic part} of some $\XRn[X]{n}$, denoted $\Xalg[x]$, is given by the union of all connected, infinite, $\overline{\R}$-\defnb subsets of $X$. That is, definable in the real field (with parameters).
\end{definition}
By our definition a few above, it is clear then that the set of interest to us is $\XtrQH[H]$, where we take all of $X$ and throw away all the `junk' bits we identify with $\Xalg[X]$. Notice that we assume our $X$ to be definable, but these partitions into algebraic and transcendental sets can be \emph{far} from definable, especially $\Xalg[x]$. Indeed, understanding each of these two sets are different problems from one another, requiring different approaches to say meaningful things. Here, we focus on $\Xtr[X]$.
\subsubsection{The Two Ingredients in Proving the \pwT Proper}
We stated it in the Introduction so as to give something to look forward to, but we now do so again -- without further ado, the \pwt:
\begin{theorem}[The \pwT]
Suppose $\XRn[X]{n}$ is a \defnb set (in our \om structure). Then for all $\eps > 0$, there exists some $c > 0$ such that for all $H \in \N$,
\begin{align*}
\card{\XtrQH[H]} \leq \bound[H].
\end{align*}
\label{thm:pwt}
\end{theorem}
Now, this right-hand side might be (should be) looking very familiar from just a moment ago -- but recall that that was for an example on \emph{all} points in the set and a special case. Here, their result is much more general and only pays attention to the transcendental parts of $X$.
Nice though it would be just to put a quick proof underneath and sate ourselves of this theorem, it does, unfortunately, require a bit more work than that. We are going to go through in the next few sections and prove the necessary constituents to our proof of \pw. The two main bits are as follows:
\begin{enumerate}
\item \textbf{The \om bit}: Suppose we have a \defnb set $X \subset (0, 1)^n$ (by normalization) and some $r \in \N$. Then there exists a set of functions, $\{ \vonevm{\phi}{k} \}$ where $\funcdom{\phi_j}{(0, 1)^{\dim{X}}}{X}$ that are $C^r$ \defnb maps such that all derivatives of each map up to degree $r$ are bounded (in modulus) by $1$ and whose union is $X$.
\label{pw_proof:pt1}
\item \textbf{The number theory bit}: Let $k, n \in \N$, $k < n$. Then for each $d \in \N$, there exists some $r \in \N$ and $c, \ \eps > 0$ with the property that if $\funcdom{\phi}{(0, 1)^k}{(0, 1)^n}$ is a $C^r$ map with derivatives bounded by $1$ up to order $r$ (note: not necessarily \defnb), and $X = \image{\phi}$, then for $G \in \N$, the set $\XQH[H]$ is contained in at most $c \cdot H^{\eps}$ algebraic hypersurfaces of degree at most $d$. Further, this $\eps \to 0$ as $d \to \infty$.
\label{pw_proof:pt2}
\end{enumerate}
In essence, this first point means that definable sets possess a certain type of parameterization, which we will come to know as \emph{cellular $r$-parameterizations}. In reference to the work we follow, the Yomdin-Gromov theorem was mentioned (which was not actually a joint work, but work continued by Gromov, inspired by Yomdin), which essentially shows this result over particular special cases. We use a newer variant, as mentioned before, which will allow us to go on to show that \pw generalizes the previously given -- first to more general \om structures, and then to further generalizations we will note (but not discuss) later on.
\begin{svgraybox}
Just as a point of note for the reader who may not have caught on, it is this second part of the proof that we have (almost \textit{ad nauseam}) been mentioning having its roots in the work between Bombieri and Pila \cite{bombieri_number_1989}.
\end{svgraybox}
Unfortunately, unlike we have seen with a couple of other multi-part results in Part I, the \pwt does \emph{not} immediately and obviously follow, even once we have these two results -- so that will take a bit of doing in and of itself. So, for the next three odd sections, we will preoccupy ourselves with proving first the \emph{\om bit}, then the \emph{\nt bit}, and finally, pulling it all together. The third and final part of this set of notes will then mention, at a very high level and without much detail, some extensions, generalizations, and applications of the \pwt and how we have seen it being used since its inception.
\subsubsection{Just a Couple of Remarks Before we Begin}
To not faff on too long, we enumerate a few remarks on what we've just started and a bit of what is to come. These remarks will not be crucial to what follows but are nonetheless of significant interest.
\begin{remark}[A Series of Remarks]
\begin{enumerate}
\item The bound given in the \pwt of $\bound[H]$ is the \emph{best} possible bound. It is already the best in the special case of Pila on curves given above -- and so this implies that $\pw$ cannot be improved over the reals. In general, the proof involves a bit more.
\item However, we often can do better in `effective' and common examples. The first point merely points out that, in general, we can come up with structures that can do no better than the general case -- but in many particular restrictions, we can do better. A good example is in $\R_{\textrm{exp}}$, where Pila conjectured that we can bound by $c \log{(H)^k}$. As well, Binyamini and Novikov \cite{binyamini_wilkies_2017} prove such a bound for $(\overline{\R}, \ \operatorname{exp}_{[0, 1]}, \ \operatorname{sin}_{[0, 1]})$, the restricted $\operatorname{exp}$ and $\operatorname{sin}$ functions. These sorts of (improved) bounds are known for many classes of sets, though very often they are \emph{not} the \defnb sets of some \om structure, requiring more restriction than we assume here.
\item The $c$ in the bound $\bound$ is \emph{not} effective -- which is to say, not easily or reasonably describable or calculable. Given that the nature of this work is often \emph{not} computational, this is not necessarily a terrible thing -- although, should it be effective, it would be the odd mathematician to be unhappy about it.
\item There are various stronger results (eg. bounds on number field degrees over $\Q$, rather than rational points), where the height function is no longer rational but algebraic. For example, consider
\begin{align*}
\card{ \ \Xtr (d, H) \ } &= \card{ \ \alpha \in X \ \colon \ [\Q(\alpha) \colon \Q] \leq d, \ H(\alpha) \leq H \ } \\
&\leq \bound[H] \textrm{ when } c = c(d).
\end{align*}
Here what we hope for (in nice structures, not in general), is something of the form
\begin{align*}
c \cdot d^k \cdot \log{(H)}^{\ell}.
\end{align*}
Such bounds also have applications that generally differ from \pw (some of which we will mention later on) To spoil that just a tinge, there is a great deal we can say about elliptic curves (and other algebraic curves, of course) in light of the \pwt.
\item Finally, there has been a good bit of work put in (and is still being put in) to the \emph{parameterization result}. This was the actual result by Yomdin that Gromov later worked on. As it turned out, of course, Pila and Wilkie could use that result (in conjunction with a good bit else) to prove the theorem this course is primarily interested in. Further improvements to these parameterization results have effective application such as, for example, the \emph{number} of $\vonevm{\phi}{k}$ needed, as a function of $r$, as stated in part (ingredient) \ref{pw_proof:pt1} in our proof of the \pwt. Or, for example, when can we do better than having these functions be $C^r$ -- such as being $C^{\infty}$ with some bound (not necessarily 1, as we have) on derivatives of all orders.
\end{enumerate}
\end{remark}
If any of these topics seemed of particular interest to you, then it will be a bit of a disappointment that we do \emph{not} discuss any of them in great detail here -- and those we do, we do so at more of a surface level than the other content presented. Of course, the references provided (and still currently worked on literature in the area) are a great place to look for further information on these topics.