-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 0
/
TPPSE1.tex
4960 lines (4539 loc) · 346 KB
/
TPPSE1.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
158
159
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
240
241
242
243
244
245
246
247
248
249
250
251
252
253
254
255
256
257
258
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
272
273
274
275
276
277
278
279
280
281
282
283
284
285
286
287
288
289
290
291
292
293
294
295
296
297
298
299
300
301
302
303
304
305
306
307
308
309
310
311
312
313
314
315
316
317
318
319
320
321
322
323
324
325
326
327
328
329
330
331
332
333
334
335
336
337
338
339
340
341
342
343
344
345
346
347
348
349
350
351
352
353
354
355
356
357
358
359
360
361
362
363
364
365
366
367
368
369
370
371
372
373
374
375
376
377
378
379
380
381
382
383
384
385
386
387
388
389
390
391
392
393
394
395
396
397
398
399
400
401
402
403
404
405
406
407
408
409
410
411
412
413
414
415
416
417
418
419
420
421
422
423
424
425
426
427
428
429
430
431
432
433
434
435
436
437
438
439
440
441
442
443
444
445
446
447
448
449
450
451
452
453
454
455
456
457
458
459
460
461
462
463
464
465
466
467
468
469
470
471
472
473
474
475
476
477
478
479
480
481
482
483
484
485
486
487
488
489
490
491
492
493
494
495
496
497
498
499
500
501
502
503
504
505
506
507
508
509
510
511
512
513
514
515
516
517
518
519
520
521
522
523
524
525
526
527
528
529
530
531
532
533
534
535
536
537
538
539
540
541
542
543
544
545
546
547
548
549
550
551
552
553
554
555
556
557
558
559
560
561
562
563
564
565
566
567
568
569
570
571
572
573
574
575
576
577
578
579
580
581
582
583
584
585
586
587
588
589
590
591
592
593
594
595
596
597
598
599
600
601
602
603
604
605
606
607
608
609
610
611
612
613
614
615
616
617
618
619
620
621
622
623
624
625
626
627
628
629
630
631
632
633
634
635
636
637
638
639
640
641
642
643
644
645
646
647
648
649
650
651
652
653
654
655
656
657
658
659
660
661
662
663
664
665
666
667
668
669
670
671
672
673
674
675
676
677
678
679
680
681
682
683
684
685
686
687
688
689
690
691
692
693
694
695
696
697
698
699
700
701
702
703
704
705
706
707
708
709
710
711
712
713
714
715
716
717
718
719
720
721
722
723
724
725
726
727
728
729
730
731
732
733
734
735
736
737
738
739
740
741
742
743
744
745
746
747
748
749
750
751
752
753
754
755
756
757
758
759
760
761
762
763
764
765
766
767
768
769
770
771
772
773
774
775
776
777
778
779
780
781
782
783
784
785
786
787
788
789
790
791
792
793
794
795
796
797
798
799
800
801
802
803
804
805
806
807
808
809
810
811
812
813
814
815
816
817
818
819
820
821
822
823
824
825
826
827
828
829
830
831
832
833
834
835
836
837
838
839
840
841
842
843
844
845
846
847
848
849
850
851
852
853
854
855
856
857
858
859
860
861
862
863
864
865
866
867
868
869
870
871
872
873
874
875
876
877
878
879
880
881
882
883
884
885
886
887
888
889
890
891
892
893
894
895
896
897
898
899
900
901
902
903
904
905
906
907
908
909
910
911
912
913
914
915
916
917
918
919
920
921
922
923
924
925
926
927
928
929
930
931
932
933
934
935
936
937
938
939
940
941
942
943
944
945
946
947
948
949
950
951
952
953
954
955
956
957
958
959
960
961
962
963
964
965
966
967
968
969
970
971
972
973
974
975
976
977
978
979
980
981
982
983
984
985
986
987
988
989
990
991
992
993
994
995
996
997
998
999
1000
\documentclass[oneside,letterpaper,12pt]{book}
\usepackage[utf8]{inputenc}
\usepackage{graphicx}
\usepackage{setspace}
\usepackage{quoting}
\usepackage{amssymb}
\usepackage{amsmath}
\usepackage{amsthm}
\usepackage[utf8]{inputenc}
\usepackage[T1]{fontenc}
\usepackage{times}
\usepackage{enumitem}
\usepackage{microtype}
%\usepackage[margin=1in]{geometry}
\usepackage[pdfencoding=unicode]{hyperref}
\usepackage[round]{natbib}
\usepackage{pifont}
\usepackage{array}
\usepackage{forest}
%\usepackage{fancyhdr}
\newcommand\titem[1]{\item{\bfseries #1}\\}
\begin{document}
\title{The Problems of Philosophy: Student Edition}
\author{\doublespacing Bertrand Russell \and editing and student notes by Landon D. C. Elkind}
\date{\today}
\frontmatter
\maketitle
\chapter*{Editor's Introduction}
This is a very lightly edited open educational resource version of \href{https://archive.org/details/theproblemsofphi00russuoft}{\emph{The Problems of Philosophy}} by \href{https://bertrandrussellsociety.org/bertrand-russell/}{Bertrand Russell}. It is lightly edited to approach (without yet meeting) the ``truer'' text of \emph{The Problems of Philosophy} \href{https://mulpress.mcmaster.ca/russelljournal/article/view/4810}{indicated by Kenneth Blackwell in the journal \emph{Russell}}.\footnote{See ``A Truer Text of \emph{The Problems of Philosophy}, \emph{Russell} Vol. 41, No. 2, pp. 78-85.} Student notes from the editor are included to make the text more suitable for college (or high school) students.
The basis for this edition is \href{https://www.gutenberg.org/cache/epub/5827/pg5827-images.html}{this 2004 version available in HTML} through \emph{Project Gutenberg}, produced by Gordon Keener and David Widger. After using \href{https://pandoc.org/}{Pandoc} to convert this HTML file into TeX, I made some aesthetic edits (like replacing Roman numerals by Arabic ones and using Arabic numerals for footnote markers). All the source files and the resulting PDF compiled in TeX are hosted on this GitHub repository and updates will be pushed there.
It is my plan to produce two descendants of this book. The first is an \emph{illustrated} (and hopefully thereby improved) student edition that includes black-and-white diagrams for the reader while retaining the instructor notes. This edition will also include excerpts from primary sources that Russell discusses in the text.
The second is a \emph{truer} edition without my notes for the student or primary sources but with Russell's index (with updated page numbers) and following the paragraph and sentence breaks in the 1967 edition published by Oxford University Press. This will also be a ``truer'' text of \emph{Problems} than any other known to me. %Both editions (like this one) will follow Blackwell's suggested emendations.
This version of \emph{The Problems of Philosophy} is published under a Creative Commons license (\href{https://creativecommons.org/licenses/by-sa/4.0/}{CC BY-SA 4.0}). The work done to produce this book was generously supported by an Affordable Textbook Initiative Grant from Western Kentucky University's Libraries. I thank the \href{http://www.russfound.org/}{Bertrand Russell Peace Foundation}, who hold the copyright to \emph{The Problems of Philosophy}, for their permission to reproduce Russell's terrific introduction to philosophy.
\begin{flushright}
Landon D. C. Elkind
\end{flushright}
\hypertarget{preface}{%
\chapter*{Preface}\label{preface}}
In the following pages I have confined myself in the main to those
problems of philosophy in regard to which I thought it possible to say
something positive and constructive, since merely negative criticism
seemed out of place. For this reason, theory of knowledge occupies a
larger space than metaphysics in the present volume, and some topics
much discussed by philosophers are treated very briefly, if at all.
I have derived valuable assistance from unpublished writings of G. E.
Moore and J. M. Keynes: from the former, as regards the relations of
sense-data to physical objects, and from the latter as regards
probability and induction. I have also profited greatly by the
criticisms and suggestions of Professor Gilbert Murray.
\bigskip
1912
\section*{Note to the Seventeenth Impression}
With reference to certain
statements on pages \pageref{China1}, \pageref{China2}, \pageref{Balfour1},
and \pageref{Balfour2}, it should be remarked that this book was
written in the early part of 1912, when China was still an empire, and
the name of the then late Prime Minister did begin with the letter B.
\bigskip
1943
\begin{flushright}
Bertrand Russell
\end{flushright}
\tableofcontents
\mainmatter
\chapter{Appearance and Reality}\label{chapter-i.-appearance-and-reality}
Is there any knowledge in the world which is so certain that no
reasonable man could doubt it? This question, which at first sight might
not seem difficult, is really one of the most difficult that can be
asked. When we have realized the obstacles in the way of a
straightforward and confident answer, we shall be well launched on the
study of philosophy---for philosophy is merely the attempt to answer
such ultimate questions, not carelessly and dogmatically, as we do in
ordinary life and even in the sciences, but critically,\label{reasons} after exploring
all that makes such questions puzzling, and after realizing all the
vagueness and confusion that underlie our ordinary ideas.
In daily life, we assume as certain many things which, on a closer
scrutiny, are found to be so full of apparent contradictions that only a
great amount of thought enables us to know what it is that we really may
believe. In the search for certainty, it is natural to begin with our
present experiences, and in some sense, no doubt, knowledge is to be
derived from them. But any statement as to what it is that our immediate
experiences make us know is very likely to be wrong. It seems to me that
I am now sitting in a chair, at a table of a certain shape, on which I
see sheets of paper with writing or print. By turning my head I see out
of the window buildings and clouds and the sun. I believe that the sun
is about ninety-three million miles from the earth; that it is a hot
globe many times bigger than the earth; that, owing to the
earth's rotation, it rises every morning, and will
continue to do so for an indefinite time in the future. I believe that,
if any other normal person comes into my room, he will see the same
chairs and tables and books and papers as I see, and that the table
which I see is the same as the table which I feel pressing against my
arm. All this seems to be so evident as to be hardly worth stating,
except in answer to a man who doubts whether I know anything. Yet all
this may be reasonably doubted, and all of it requires much careful
discussion before we can be sure that we have stated it in a form that
is wholly true.
To make our difficulties plain, let us concentrate attention on the
table. To the eye it is oblong, brown and shiny, to the touch it is
smooth and cool and hard; when I tap it, it gives out a wooden sound.
Any one else who sees and feels and hears the table will agree with this
description, so that it might seem as if no difficulty would arise; but
as soon as we try to be more precise our troubles begin. Although I
believe that the table is `really' of
the same colour all over, the parts that reflect the light look much
brighter than the other parts, and some parts look white because of
reflected light. I know that, if I move, the parts that reflect the
light will be different, so that the apparent distribution of colours on
the table will change. It follows that if several people are looking at
the table at the same moment, no two of them will see exactly the same
distribution of colours, because no two can see it from exactly the same
point of view, and any change in the point of view makes some change in
the way the light is reflected.
For most practical purposes these differences are unimportant, but to
the painter they are all-important: the painter has to unlearn the habit
of thinking that things seem to have the colour which common sense says
they `really' have, and to learn the
habit of seeing things as they appear. Here we have already the
beginning of one of the distinctions that cause most trouble in
philosophy---the distinction between
`appearance' and
`reality', between what things seem to be
and what they are. The painter wants to know what things seem to be, the
practical man and the philosopher want to know what they are; but the
philosopher's wish to know this is stronger than the
practical man's, and is more troubled by knowledge as to
the difficulties of answering the question.
To return to the table. \label{evident} It is evident from what we have found, that
there is no colour which pre-eminently appears to be \emph{the} colour
of the table, or even of any one particular part of the table---it
appears to be of different colours from different points of view, and
there is no reason for regarding some of these as more really its colour
than others. And we know that even from a given point of view the colour
will seem different by artificial light, or to a colour-blind man, or to
a man wearing blue spectacles, while in the dark there will be no colour
at all, though to touch and hearing the table will be unchanged. This
colour is not something which is inherent in the table, but something
depending upon the table and the spectator and the way the light falls
on the table. When, in ordinary life, we speak of \emph{the} colour of
the table, we only mean the sort of colour which it will seem to have to
a normal spectator from an ordinary point of view under usual conditions
of light. But the other colours which appear under other conditions have
just as good a right to be considered real; and therefore, to avoid
favouritism, we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has any
one particular colour.
The same thing applies to the texture. With the naked eye one can see
the grain, but otherwise the table looks smooth and even. If we looked
at it through a microscope, we should see roughnesses and hills and
valleys, and all sorts of differences that are imperceptible to the
naked eye. Which of these is the `real'
table? We are naturally tempted to say that what we see through the
microscope is more real, but that in turn would be changed by a still
more powerful microscope. If, then, we cannot trust what we see with the
naked eye, why should we trust what we see through a microscope? Thus,
again, the confidence in our senses with which we began deserts us.
The shape of the table is no better. We are all in the habit of judging
as to the `real' shapes of things, and
we do this so unreflectingly that we come to think we actually see the
real shapes. But, in fact, as we all have to learn if we try to draw, a
given thing looks different in shape from every different point of view.
If our table is `really' rectangular,
it will look, from almost all points of view, as if it had two acute
angles and two obtuse angles. If opposite sides are parallel, they will
look as if they converged to a point away from the spectator; if they
are of equal length, they will look as if the nearer side were longer.
All these things are not commonly noticed in looking at a table, because
experience has taught us to construct the
`real' shape from the apparent shape,
and the `real' shape is what interests
us as practical men. But the `real'
shape is not what we see; it is something inferred from what we see. And
what we see is constantly changing in shape as we move about the room;
so that here again the senses seem not to give us the truth about the
table itself, but only about the appearance of the table.
Similar difficulties arise when we consider the sense of touch. It is
true that the table always gives us a sensation of hardness, and we feel
that it resists pressure. But the sensation we obtain depends upon how
hard we press the table and also upon what part of the body we press
with; thus the various sensations due to various pressures or various
parts of the body cannot be supposed to reveal \emph{directly} any
definite property of the table, but at most to be \emph{signs} of some
property which perhaps \emph{causes} all the sensations, but is not
actually apparent in any of them. And the same applies still more
obviously to the sounds which can be elicited by rapping the table.
Thus it becomes evident that the real table, if there is one, is not the
same as what we immediately experience by sight or touch or hearing. The
real table, if there is one, is not \emph{immediately} known to us at
all, but must be an inference from what is immediately known. Hence, two
very difficult questions at once arise; namely, (1) Is there a real
table at all? (2) If so, what sort of object can it be?
It will help us in considering these questions to have a few simple
terms of which the meaning is definite and clear. Let us give the name
of `sense-data' to the things that are
immediately known in sensation: such things as colours, sounds, smells,
hardnesses, roughnesses, and so on. We shall give the name
`sensation' to the experience of being
immediately aware of these things. Thus, whenever we see a colour, we
have a sensation \emph{of} the colour, but the colour itself is a
sense-datum, not a sensation. The colour is that \emph{of} which we are
immediately aware, and the awareness itself is the sensation. It is
plain that if we are to know anything about the table, it must be by
means of the sense-data---brown colour, oblong shape, smoothness,
etc.---which we associate with the table; but, for the reasons which
have been given, we cannot say that the table is the sense-data, or even
that the sense-data are directly properties of the table. Thus a problem
arises as to the relation of the sense-data to the real table, supposing
there is such a thing.
The real table, if it exists, we will call a `physical
object'. Thus we have to consider the relation of
sense-data to physical objects. The collection of all physical objects
is called `matter'. Thus our two
questions may be re-stated as follows: (1) Is there any such thing as
matter? (2) If so, what is its nature?
The philosopher who first brought prominently forward the reasons for
regarding the immediate objects of our senses as not existing
independently of us was \href{https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/berkeley/}
{Bishop Berkeley} (1685-1753). His \href{https://archive.org/details/threedialoguesbe00berkiala}
{\emph{Three Dialogues between Hylas and Philonous, in Opposition to Sceptics and Atheists}},
undertake to prove that there is no such thing as matter at
all, and that the world consists of nothing but minds and their ideas.
Hylas has hitherto believed in matter, but he is no match for Philonous,
who mercilessly drives him into contradictions and paradoxes, and makes
his own denial of matter seem, in the end, as if it were almost common
sense. The arguments employed are of very different value: some are
important and sound, others are confused or quibbling. But Berkeley
retains the merit of having shown that the existence of matter is
capable of being denied without absurdity, and that if there are any
things that exist independently of us they cannot be the immediate
objects of our sensations.
There are two different questions involved when we ask whether matter
exists, and it is important to keep them clear. We commonly mean by
`matter' something which is opposed to
`mind', something which we think of as
occupying space and as radically incapable of any sort of thought or
consciousness. It is chiefly in this sense that Berkeley denies matter;
that is to say, he does not deny that the sense-data which we commonly
take as signs of the existence of the table are really signs of the
existence of \emph{something} independent of us, but he does deny that
this something is non-mental, that it is neither mind nor ideas
entertained by some mind. He admits that there must be something which
continues to exist when we go out of the room or shut our eyes, and that
what we call seeing the table does really give us reason for believing
in something which persists even when we are not seeing it. But he
thinks that this something cannot be radically different in nature from
what we see, and cannot be independent of seeing altogether, though it
must be independent of \emph{our} seeing. He is thus led to regard the
`real' table as an idea in the mind of
God. Such an idea has the required permanence and independence of
ourselves, without being---as matter would otherwise be---something
quite unknowable, in the sense that we can only infer it, and can never
be directly and immediately aware of it.
Other philosophers since Berkeley have also held that, although the
table does not depend for its existence upon being seen by me, it does
depend upon being seen (or otherwise apprehended in sensation) by
\emph{some} mind---not necessarily the mind of God, but more often the
whole collective mind of the universe. This they hold, as Berkeley does,
chiefly because they think there can be nothing real---or at any rate
nothing known to be real except minds and their thoughts and feelings.
We might state the argument by which they support their view in some
such way as this: `Whatever can be thought of is an idea
in the mind of the person thinking of it; therefore nothing can be
thought of except ideas in minds; therefore anything else is
inconceivable, and what is inconceivable cannot exist.'
Such an argument, in my opinion, is fallacious; and of course those who
advance it do not put it so shortly or so crudely. But whether valid or
not, the argument has been very widely advanced in one form or another;
and very many philosophers, perhaps a majority, have held that there is
nothing real except minds and their ideas. Such philosophers are called
`idealists'. When they come to explaining
matter, they either say, like Berkeley, that matter is really nothing
but a collection of ideas, or they say, like
\href{https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/leibniz/}{Leibniz} (1646-1716), that
what appears as matter is really a collection of more or less
rudimentary minds.
But these philosophers, though they deny matter as opposed to mind,
nevertheless, in another sense, admit matter. It will be remembered that
we asked two questions; namely, (1) Is there a real table at all? (2) If
so, what sort of object can it be? Now both Berkeley and Leibniz admit
that there is a real table, but Berkeley says it is certain ideas in the
mind of God, and Leibniz says it is a colony of souls. Thus both of them
answer our first question in the affirmative, and only diverge from the
views of ordinary mortals in their answer to our second question. \label{Q1} In
fact, almost all philosophers seem to be agreed that there is a real
table: they almost all agree that, however much our sense-data---colour,
shape, smoothness, etc.---may depend upon us, yet their occurrence is a
sign of something existing independently of us, something differing,
perhaps, completely from our sense-data, and yet to be regarded as
causing those sense-data whenever we are in a suitable relation to the
real table.
Now obviously this point in which the philosophers are agreed---the view
that there \emph{is} a real table, whatever its nature may be---is
vitally important, and it will be worth while to consider what reasons
there are for accepting this view before we go on to the further
question as to the nature of the real table. Our next chapter,
therefore, will be concerned with the reasons for supposing that there
is a real table at all.
Before we go farther it will be well to consider for a moment what it is
that we have discovered so far. It has appeared that, if we take any
common object of the sort that is supposed to be known by the senses,
what the senses \emph{immediately} tell us is not the truth about the
object as it is apart from us, but only the truth about certain
sense-data which, so far as we can see, depend upon the relations
between us and the object. Thus what we directly see and feel is merely
`appearance', which we believe to be a
sign of some `reality' behind. But if
the reality is not what appears, have we any means of knowing whether
there is any reality at all? And if so, have we any means of finding out
what it is like?
Such questions are bewildering, and it is difficult to know that even
the strangest hypotheses may not be true. Thus our familiar table, which
has roused but the slightest thoughts in us hitherto, has become a
problem full of surprising possibilities. The one thing we know about it
is that it is not what it seems. Beyond this modest result, so far, we
have the most complete liberty of conjecture. Leibniz tells us it is a
community of souls: Berkeley tells us it is an idea in the mind of God;
sober science, scarcely less wonderful, tells us it is a vast collection
of electric charges in violent motion.
Among these surprising possibilities, doubt suggests that perhaps there
is no table at all. Philosophy, if it cannot \emph{answer} so many
questions as we could wish, has at least the power of \emph{asking}
questions which increase the interest of the world, and show the
strangeness and wonder lying just below the surface even in the
commonest things of daily life.
\protect\hypertarget{link2HCH0002}{}{}
\pagebreak
\section{Notes for the Student}
\markboth{CHAPTER 1 NOTES}{CHAPTER 1 NOTES}
\section*{A bit about philosophers}
Philosophers, like everyone else, often use arguments to critically study things around them. In fact philosophers are expected to use arguments professionally. But of course! Everyone uses arguments in daily life and as a vital part of whatever career they are in. And philosophers, like everyone you would \emph{want} as a friend, are (supposed to be) curious and invested in figuring out which beliefs are true. In these ways philosophers are just like everyone else (is supposed to be).
But philosophers are not like everyone else in that they take no particular claim for granted, and they do this professionally. This means that philosophers in their practice can critically discuss \emph{any given premise} in a particular argument. They usually critically discuss some premise when the person they are talking to either does not believe it is true or does not understand \emph{why} we think it is true. The latter case actually occurs more often than the first one. Most philosophers do not reject all the claims that we ordinarily take for granted. But they are curious about what we should say if we were really pressed on the subject. This is because, as Russell says (page \pageref{reasons}), philosophers want to know what is the case \textit{with reasons}.
In other words, we philosophize about what we believe already and it is not in serious doubt. But philosophizing about what we believe, even confidently, is still valuable for two reasons. First, we might end up rejecting what we thought was true after careful reflection. This has often happened (haven't you ever changed your mind before - maybe even more than once?). Second, even if we come back to our starting point, the philosophical journey around our beliefs will still have helped us understand what we believe and why more clearly.
Philosophers' openness to questioning everything has caused people to form two false views about philosophers. The first is that philosophers are very destructive and question everything we believe, always asking another `why' question, until nothing is left. But this comes from a misunderstanding of what good philosophers do. Arguing well requires finding premises that another person will accept. Any child can (and some do) reject every premise you give them. That is not philosophizing and takes no skill. It takes philosophical skill to offer premises you take for granted and lead you, step by undeniable step, to a conclusion that you perhaps did not intend to accept, or even one that you find unbelievable. Critical arguments, which are the only ones worth having, are always a conversation, even when you have them with just yourself. Remember what who the conversational argument is with, what is valuable about the conversational argument to its participants, and whether the conversational argument is worth continuing to you.
The second false view about philosophers is that philosophers achieve nothing: they just negatively question everything that even a reasonable person would deny. This could not be further from the truth. Philosophizing is the beating heart of every scientific discipline and practice---political science, physics, biology, chemistry, computer science, engineering, psychology, economics, medicine, mathematics, and so on. Sea change almost always occurs in any scientific discipline because someone had a philosophical thought that they wanted to lift off the ground. Philosophy moreover touches upon humanistic questions that themselves spring from that same deep well of human experience and feeling which inspires all activism, art, music, literature, poetry, film, and theater that makes life worth living. As long as humans have been around, the world has been littered with the achievements of philosophers, including scientific disciplines themselves, and with timeless humanistic and social feats, from the grandiose like the invention of democracy to the mundane like an ordinary existential crisis.
To take an example of philosophy's achievements that you can (and probably did just today) fit into your hand: we have the universal computer (of which your laptop and cell phones are instances) because of Alan Turing. Turing's achievement owes deep intellectually debts to philosophers, including this book's author. First, Turing's work on the foundations of mathematics and computation occurred in the Cambridge mathematical logic tradition that Russell advanced with his co-authored \emph{Principia Mathematica}. Turing's motivation for working on universal computers partly came from the Incompleteness Theorems of Kurt G\"odel, who initially proved his famous theorems by encoding Russell's co-authored \emph{Principia Mathematica} in the natural numbers. Second, Turing's model for computability, the \emph{Turing machine}, comes from a philosophical analysis of what human beings can compute. This philosophical analysis led to a conjecture we now call \emph{Turing's thesis} that all computable processes (in the philosophical sense of `computable') are computable by Turing machines (whether Turing's model of a universal computer or an equivalent one). We do not know if this thesis is true or not---we have no counterexamples yet---but we do know that Turing's philosophizing, his philosophical analysis of computability, is what gave us the universal computer.
So from now on, every time your phone notification disturbs you, remember that you have a philosopher to thank (or curse). Likewise, every time you vote, exercise your human rights, consider whether the needs of the many outweigh the needs of the few, and so on, you have a philosopher to thank. Thus philosophy is highly productive and not just destructive. Let us continue to doing it.
\section*{Arguments}
The most vivid example of how philosophers take no particular claim for granted is the problem of perception. How do we know that when we look around the world, or listen around it (in polite company), or sniff around it (in impolite company), that what we experience is really there? When you are walking with a friend, neither you nor your friend is bewildered by your perceptions. You both just take it for granted that when you see a tree, it is not a scam by the government or a corporation; it is not a dream or a hallucination; it is just a plain old tree.
Almost nobody seriously denies it. But it becomes surprisingly hard to come up with a really knockdown argument for trees just being a tree. This is because it is always \emph{possible}---at least logically possible---that your perceptions are leading you into false beliefs about the world. Think about any vivid dream you had that was fantastically or just plain fictional. You may have seen, heard, tasted, touched, or smelled things in your dream that were not there. It may have even felt almost as vivid and real as waking life. So, given that you \emph{can} be wrong about your perceptions in any given case, what makes you \emph{sure} beyond a reasonable doubt that the ones in waking life are not a clever trick being played upon you?
These questions can feel bewildering, especially if you are seriously considering them for the first time. Russell's first chapter helps us begin to understand how to approach these questions as philosophers do---through arguments.
An \emph{argument} is just a collection of claims. One of these claims is a conclusion. The rest of the claims are premises offered in support of the conclusion. If I tell you, ``You should do your philosophy reading because you promised to do so,'' this would be an argument. The conclusion is that you should do your philosophy reading. The (explicit) premise is that you promised to do your philosophy reading. The unstated (implicit) premise is that if you promised to do your philosophy reading, then you should do your philosophy reading.
To help us study arguments, let us introduce two common patterns of argument. The first is \emph{modus ponens}, and says that given a \textit{conditional} (if-then claim) and its \textit{antecedent} (the left side or `if' side of the if-then claim) as premises, then its \textit{consequent} (the right side or `then' side of the if-then claim) is also given as a conclusion.
\begin{center}
\textbf{Modus Ponens}
\end{center}
\begin{enumerate}
\item If P is true, then Q is true. \hfill Premise
\item P is true. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, Q is true. \hfill 1, 2 MP
\end{enumerate}
The second is \emph{modus tollens}, and says that given a conditional and the negation of its consequent as premises, then the negation of its antecedent is also given as a conclusion.
\begin{center}
\textbf{Modus Tollens}
\end{center}
\begin{enumerate}
\item If P is true, then Q is true. \hfill Premise
\item Q is not true. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, P is not true. \hfill 1, 2 MT
\end{enumerate}
In restating a philosopher's argument, it is helpful to put arguments in one of these forms. This is because these argument forms are \textit{deductively valid}: it is impossible (in a logical sense) for the premises to be true while the conclusion is false. In an argument that has the special property of being valid, any world in which the premises are true is automatically one in which the conclusion is true. So in arguments that are deductively valid, the truth of the premises is enough to guarantee (in a logical sense) the truth of the conclusion.
Valid arguments are only good hypothetically. They are as good as their premises. Consider this valid argument:
\begin{enumerate}
\item All humans are mammals.
\item All mammals are animals.
\item So, all humans are animals.
\end{enumerate}
This seems like a great argument, but validity is not enough to make a good argument. This valid argument only counts as a good one because the premises are highly likely to be true. We have good reason to think that all humans are mammals and that all mammals are animals (from a generalizations that are well supported by repeated observation).
Now consider the following argument:
\begin{enumerate}
\item All humans are fish.
\item All fish have gills.
\item So, all humans have gills.
\end{enumerate}
This argument is valid just like the previous one. It follows the exact same pattern of reasoning. But we have good reason to think that premise (1) is false (by direct observation). So it is a bad argument.
The key to a good argument is that you want two features: (1) it is valid; (2) it has premises that are true. Condition (1) can be readily met once you get some practice. Condition (2) is harder to meet because it can often be controversial whether the premises are in fact true.
Consider the following argument as an example:
\begin{enumerate}
\item Daniel Tiger is a cat.
\item All cats are good.
\item So, Daniel Tiger is good.
\end{enumerate}
This is another valid argument pattern. So it meets condition (1) for being a good argument. What about condition (2)? Are all the premises true? This is harder to judge. Daniel Tiger is definitely a cat because he is a tiger. Is it really the case, though, that all cats are good? I am sure that a quick internet search will provide some evidence to the contrary. (All dogs are good, though, not to worry.)
Let us return to our first argument: ``You should do your philosophy reading because you promised to do so.'' Putting this into \emph{modus ponens} format can help us understand and analyze this argument.
\begin{enumerate}
\item You promised to do your philosophy reading.
\item If you promised to do your philosophy reading, then you should do your philosophy reading.
\item So, you should do your philosophy reading.
\end{enumerate}
Remember, the second premise was unstated (implicit) but the person offering this argument likely meant to link premise (1) to the conclusion using \emph{some} such claim like premise (2). This argument is definitely valid because it follows the \emph{modus ponens} pattern. Does this argument meet condition (2)? Are its premises true?
We can verify or falsify premise (1). We can ask whether you promised, or see if there is a record of your promising (like if you promised to do your reading in a courtroom or if you signed a document promising to do the reading).
It is harder to verify premise (2). Can we imagine a case where you promised to do something but we thought that you could (or maybe should) break your promise? I may promise to grade your homework within two weeks of the due date, but if I get hit by a campus bus and lapse into a coma, we might think it is excusable for me to break my promise in that case (I could hardly do anything else). There are lots of trying circumstance we could imagine life throwing at someone that causes them not to do the reading. And in a lot of these cases, we would not think you should do your philosophy reading because you need to take care of yourself first.
So premise (2) looks false. But what about this alternative? (2a): ``If you promised to do your philosophy reading \emph{and} there was no cause that would understandably absolve you of keeping your promise, then you should do your philosophy reading.'' This looks like it is on the right track. Then there are philosophical questions about what sorts of causes absolve you of promise-keeping. But now the premise looks at least plausibly true: if we replace premise (2) with premise (2a), we have a good argument.
There are three morals to take away from this brief discussion of arguments. First, a good argument follows a valid pattern and has true premises. (Actually, there are good arguments, which are common in daily life, that are not quite valid but there is still strong support between the premises and conclusion. We will talk about those again much later in the book.) Second, if you are confronted with an argument of this kind---one that is deductively valid---the only way to reject its conclusion (if you find it to be one that should be rejected) is to argue that its premises are untrue. Third, putting arguments into the \emph{modus ponens} pattern can help us understand the argument better, both by making our conversation partner state for us what premises they left unstated in their thinking and by helping us identify and attend to those premises we do not agree to just yet.
Again, in a valid argument, it is necessary that the conclusion is true \textit{if} the premises are all true. So if you think that the conclusion is not true, then you have to consider which of the premises is not true. And the benefit of putting another philosopher's argument in a deductively valid form is to make clear what the premises are, so that you can critically consider them. It helps you understand and evaluate an argument, and to do so \textit{critically}---as a philosopher should.
\section*{Back to the book you were reading}
Let us now apply this to Russell's argumentation in Chapter 1. In Chapter 1, having made the appearance-reality distinction, Russell argues that how things appear to us is distinct from how things are. What is his argument for this view? Now Russell says the following (\pageref{evident}):
\begin{quote}
It is evident from what we have found, that there is no colour which preeminently appears to be \textit{the} colour of the table, or even of any one particular part of the table---it appears to be of different colours from different points of view, and there is no reason for regarding some of these as more really its colour than others. [...] When, in ordinary life, we speak of \textit{the} colour of the table, we only mean the sort of colour which it will seem to have to a normal spectator from an ordinary point of view under usual conditions of light. But the other colours which appear under other conditions have just as good a right to be considered real; and therefore, to avoid favouritism, we are compelled to deny that, in itself, the table has any one particular colour.
\end{quote}
Now this is a blob of text. Let us try to put it in one of the above argument forms.
\begin{enumerate}
\item The table appears differently from different points of view. \hfill Premise
\item If the table appears differently from different points of view, then there is no good reason for regarding any one appearance of the table as its real one. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, there is no good reason for regarding any one appearance of the table as its real one. \hfill 1, 2 MP
\end{enumerate}
This is really nice! Now we know which premises to attack if we want to rationally reject the conclusion (although we might perhaps be convinced by Russell's argument of the need to separate the table's appearances from how it really is). Nobody reasonable will reject (1). \\
\par But what about (2)? Might that be rejected? Here is an attempt:
\begin{quote}
Maybe we do not need to identify \textit{one} of the appearances as the real one. Why not say that \textit{many} of the appearances---perhaps \textit{all} of them---are equally real? %So the real table just is all of its appearances?
\end{quote}
Russell does not address this objection. And there is a good reason why not. It leads to a really undesirable conclusion in the following way:
\begin{enumerate}
\item If the appearances of the table are all the one real table, then the appearances are the same object. \hfill Premise
\item If the appearances are the same object, then the appearances have all the same properties. \hfill Premise (Leibniz)
\item The apperances do not have all the same properties. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, the appearances are not the same same object. \hfill 2, 3 MT
\item Thus, the appearances of the table are all the one real table. \hfill 1, 4 MT
\end{enumerate}
This is nice! Now we know what premises to attack, if any. Presumably, no reasonable person will dispute (3), nor even (2). So one needs to consider (1) in evaluating this argument.
Notice also that this argument has \textit{two} inferences. It has an intermediate conclusion in (4) before the final conclusion in (5). A lot of philosophical arguments work that way.
\hypertarget{chapter-ii.-the-existence-of-matter}{%
\chapter{The Existence of Matter}\label{chapter-ii.-the-existence-of-matter}}
In this chapter we have to ask ourselves whether, in any sense at all,
there is such a thing as matter. Is there a table which has a certain
intrinsic nature, and continues to exist when I am not looking, or is
the table merely a product of my imagination, a dream-table in a very
prolonged dream? This question is of the greatest importance. For if we
cannot be sure of the independent existence of objects, we cannot be
sure of the independent existence of other people's
bodies, and therefore still less of other people's
minds, since we have no grounds for believing in their minds except such
as are derived from observing their bodies. Thus if we cannot be sure of
the independent existence of objects, we shall be left alone in a
desert---it may be that the whole outer world is nothing but a dream,
and that we alone exist. This is an uncomfortable possibility; but
although it cannot be strictly proved to be false, there is not the
slightest reason to suppose that it is true. \label{proof} In this chapter we have to
see why this is the case.
Before we embark upon doubtful matters, let us try to find some more or
less fixed point from which to start. Although we are doubting the
physical existence of the table, we are not doubting the existence of
the sense-data which made us think there was a table; we are not
doubting that, while we look, a certain colour and shape appear to us,
and while we press, a certain sensation of hardness is experienced by
us. All this, which is psychological, we are not calling in question. In
fact, whatever else may be doubtful, some at least of our immediate
experiences seem absolutely certain.
\href{https://plato.stanford.edu/entries/descartes/}{Descartes} (1596-1650), the founder of modern philosophy, invented a
method which may still be used with profit---the method of systematic
doubt. \label{doubt} He determined that he would believe nothing which he did not see
quite clearly and distinctly to be true. Whatever he could bring himself
to doubt, he would doubt, until he saw reason for not doubting it. By
applying this method he gradually became convinced that the only
existence of which he could be \emph{quite} certain was his own. He
imagined a deceitful demon, who presented unreal things to his senses in
a perpetual phantasmagoria; it might be very improbable that such a
demon existed, but still it was possible, and therefore doubt concerning
things perceived by the senses was possible.
But doubt concerning his own existence was not possible, for if he did
not exist, no demon could deceive him. If he doubted, he must exist; if
he had any experiences whatever, he must exist. Thus his own existence
was an absolute certainty to him. `I think, therefore I
am,' he said (\emph{Cogito, ergo sum}); and on the
basis of this certainty he set to work to build up again the world of
knowledge which his doubt had laid in ruins. By inventing the method of
doubt, and by showing that subjective things are the most certain,
Descartes performed a great service to philosophy, and one which makes
him still useful to all students of the subject.
But some care is needed in using Descartes' argument.
`I think, therefore I am' says rather
more than is strictly certain. It might seem as though we were quite
sure of being the same person to-day as we were yesterday, and this is
no doubt true in some sense. But the real Self is as hard to arrive at
as the real table, and does not seem to have that absolute, convincing
certainty that belongs to particular experiences. \label{self} When I look at my
table and see a certain brown colour, what is quite certain at once is
not '\emph{I} am seeing a brown colour',
but rather, `a brown colour is being
seen'. This of course involves something (or somebody)
which (or who) sees the brown colour; but it does not of itself involve
that more or less permanent person whom we call
`I'. So far as immediate certainty goes,
it might be that the something which sees the brown colour is quite
momentary, and not the same as the something which has some different
experience the next moment.
Thus it is our particular thoughts and feelings that have primitive
certainty. And this applies to dreams and hallucinations as well as to
normal perceptions: when we dream or see a ghost, we certainly do have
the sensations we think we have, but for various reasons it is held that
no physical object corresponds to these sensations. Thus the certainty
of our knowledge of our own experiences does not have to be limited in
any way to allow for exceptional cases. Here, therefore, we have, for
what it is worth, a solid basis from which to begin our pursuit of
knowledge.
The problem we have to consider is this: Granted that we are certain of
our own sense-data, have we any reason for regarding them as signs of
the existence of something else, which we can call the physical object?
When we have enumerated all the sense-data which we should naturally
regard as connected with the table, have we said all there is to say
about the table, or is there still something else---something not a
sense-datum, something which persists when we go out of the room? Common
sense unhesitatingly answers that there is. What can be bought and sold
and pushed about and have a cloth laid on it, and so on, cannot be a
\emph{mere} collection of sense-data. If the cloth completely hides the
table, we shall derive no sense-data from the table, and therefore, if
the table were merely sense-data, it would have ceased to exist, and the
cloth would be suspended in empty air, resting, by a miracle, in the
place where the table formerly was. This seems plainly absurd; but
whoever wishes to become a philosopher must learn not to be frightened
by absurdities.
One great reason why it is felt that we must secure a physical object in
addition to the sense-data, is that we want the same object for
different people. When ten people are sitting round a dinner-table, it
seems preposterous to maintain that they are not seeing the same
tablecloth, the same knives and forks and spoons and glasses. But the
sense-data are private to each separate person; what is immediately
present to the sight of one is not immediately present to the sight of
another: they all see things from slightly different points of view, and
therefore see them slightly differently. Thus, if there are to be public
neutral objects, which can be in some sense known to many different
people, there must be something over and above the private and
particular sense-data which appear to various people. What reason, then,
have we for believing that there are such public neutral objects?
The first answer that naturally occurs to one is that, although
different people may see the table slightly differently, still they all
see more or less similar things when they look at the table, and the
variations in what they see follow the laws of perspective and
reflection of light, so that it is easy to arrive at a permanent object
underlying all the different people's sense-data. I
bought my table from the former occupant of my room; I could not buy
\emph{his} sense-data, which died when he went away, but I could and did
buy the confident expectation of more or less similar sense-data. Thus
it is the fact that different people have similar sense-data, and that
one person in a given place at different times has similar sense-data,
which makes us suppose that over and above the sense-data there is a
permanent public object which underlies or causes the sense-data of
various people at various times.
Now in so far as the above considerations depend upon supposing that
there are other people besides ourselves, they beg the very question at
issue. Other people are represented to me by certain sense-data, such as
the sight of them or the sound of their voices, and if I had no reason
to believe that there were physical objects independent of my
sense-data, I should have no reason to believe that other people exist
except as part of my dream. Thus, when we are trying to show that there
must be objects independent of our own sense-data, we cannot appeal to
the testimony of other people, since this testimony itself consists of
sense-data, and does not reveal other people's
experiences unless our own sense-data are signs of things existing
independently of us. We must therefore, if possible, find, in our own
purely private experiences, characteristics which show, or tend to show,
that there are in the world things other than ourselves and our private
experiences.
In one sense it must be admitted that we can never prove the existence
of things other than ourselves and our experiences. No logical absurdity
results from the hypothesis that the world consists of myself and my
thoughts and feelings and sensations, and that everything else is mere
fancy. In dreams a very complicated world may seem to be present, and
yet on waking we find it was a delusion; that is to say, we find that
the sense-data in the dream do not appear to have corresponded with such
physical objects as we should naturally infer from our sense-data. (It
is true that, when the physical world is assumed, it is possible to find
physical causes for the sense-data in dreams: a door banging, for
instance, may cause us to dream of a naval engagement. \label{navy} But although, in
this case, there is a physical cause for the sense-data, there is not a
physical object corresponding to the sense-data in the way in which an
actual naval battle would correspond.) There is no logical impossibility
in the supposition that the whole of life is a dream, in which we
ourselves create all the objects that come before us. But although this
is not logically impossible, there is no reason whatever to suppose that
it is true; and it is, in fact, a less simple hypothesis, viewed as a
means of accounting for the facts of our own life, than the common-sense
hypothesis that there really are objects independent of us, whose action
on us causes our sensations.
The way in which simplicity comes in from supposing that there really
are physical objects is easily seen. \label{kitty} If the cat appears at one moment in
one part of the room, and at another in another part, it is natural to
suppose that it has moved from the one to the other, passing over a
series of intermediate positions. But if it is merely a set of
sense-data, it cannot have ever been in any place where I did not see
it; thus we shall have to suppose that it did not exist at all while I
was not looking, but suddenly sprang into being in a new place. If the
cat exists whether I see it or not, we can understand from our own
experience how it gets hungry between one meal and the next; but if it
does not exist when I am not seeing it, it seems odd that appetite
should grow during non-existence as fast as during existence. And if the
cat consists only of sense-data, it cannot be hungry, since no hunger
but my own can be a sense-datum to me. Thus the behaviour of the
sense-data which represent the cat to me, though it seems quite natural
when regarded as an expression of hunger, becomes utterly inexplicable
when regarded as mere movements and changes of patches of colour, which
are as incapable of hunger as a triangle is of playing football.
But the difficulty in the case of the cat is nothing compared to the
difficulty in the case of human beings. When human beings speak---that
is, when we hear certain noises which we associate with ideas, and
simultaneously see certain motions of lips and expressions of face---it
is very difficult to suppose that what we hear is not the expression of
a thought, as we know it would be if we emitted the same sounds. Of
course similar things happen in dreams, where we are mistaken as to the
existence of other people. But dreams are more or less suggested by what
we call waking life, and are capable of being more or less accounted for
on scientific principles if we assume that there really is a physical
world. Thus every principle of simplicity urges us to adopt the natural
view, that there really are objects other than our selves and our
sense-data which have an existence not dependent upon our perceiving
them.
Of course it is not by argument that we originally come by our belief in
an independent external world. We find this belief ready in ourselves as
soon as we begin to reflect: it is what may be called an
\emph{instinctive} belief. \label{instinctive} We should never have been led to question
this belief but for the fact that, at any rate in the case of sight, it
seems as if the sense-datum itself were instinctively believed to be the
independent object, whereas argument shows that the object cannot be
identical with the sense-datum. This discovery, however---which is not
at all paradoxical in the case of taste and smell and sound, and only
slightly so in the case of touch---leaves undiminished our instinctive
belief that there \emph{are} objects \emph{corresponding} to our
sense-data. Since this belief does not lead to any difficulties, but on
the contrary tends to simplify and systematize our account of our
experiences, there seems no good reason for rejecting it. We may
therefore admit---though with a slight doubt derived from dreams---that
the external world does really exist, and is not wholly dependent for
its existence upon our continuing to perceive it.
The argument which has led us to this conclusion is doubtless less
strong than we could wish, but it is typical of many philosophical
arguments, and it is therefore worth while to consider briefly its
general character and validity. All knowledge, we find, must be built up
upon our instinctive beliefs, and if these are rejected, nothing is
left. But among our instinctive beliefs some are much stronger than
others, while many have, by habit and association, become entangled with
other beliefs, not really instinctive, but falsely supposed to be part
of what is believed instinctively.
Philosophy should show us the hierarchy of our instinctive beliefs,
beginning with those we hold most strongly, and presenting each as much
isolated and as free from irrelevant additions as possible. It should
take care to show that, in the form in which they are finally set forth,
our instinctive beliefs do not clash, but form a harmonious system.
There can never be any reason for rejecting one instinctive belief
except that it clashes with others; thus, if they are found to
harmonize, the whole system becomes worthy of acceptance.
It is of course \emph{possible} that all or any of our beliefs may be
mistaken, and therefore all ought to be held with at least some slight
element of doubt. But we cannot have \emph{reason} to reject a belief
except on the ground of some other belief. Hence, by organizing our
instinctive beliefs and their consequences, by considering which among
them it is most possible, if necessary, to modify or abandon, we can
arrive, on the basis of accepting as our sole data what we instinctively
believe, at an orderly systematic organization of our knowledge, in
which, though the \emph{possibility} of error remains, its likelihood is
diminished by the interrelation of the parts and by the critical
scrutiny which has preceded acquiescence.
This function, at least, philosophy can perform. Most philosophers,
rightly or wrongly, believe that philosophy can do much more than
this---that it can give us knowledge, not otherwise attainable,
concerning the universe as a whole, and concerning the nature of
ultimate reality. Whether this be the case or not, the more modest
function we have spoken of can certainly be performed by philosophy, and
certainly suffices, for those who have once begun to doubt the adequacy
of common sense, to justify the arduous and difficult labours that
philosophical problems involve.
\protect\hypertarget{link2HCH0003}{}{}
\pagebreak
\section{Notes for the Student}
\markboth{CHAPTER 2 NOTES}{CHAPTER 2 NOTES}
\par Recall Russell's argument, which we put into the \emph{modus ponens} pattern below, for an object's appearances being distinct from its underlying reality:
\begin{enumerate}
\item The table appears differently from different points of view.\hfill Premise
\item If the table appears differently from different points of view, then there is no good reason for regarding any one appearance of the table as its real one.\hfill Premise
\item Thus, there is no good reason for regarding any one appearance of the table as its real one. \hfill 1, 2 MP
\end{enumerate}
Russell now asks us to consider whether there is any underlying reality at all. This is his question (1) Is there any such thing as matter? Now most philosophers, like most people, believe that there is an underlying reality. They just disagree over what it is like (\pageref{Q1}).
\par Russell praises Descrates for ``the method of systematic doubt" because, besides being a great method, it shows ``that the subjective things are the most certain" (\pageref{doubt}).
\par What is this method, then? Here is Descrates in the \textit{Meditations}:
\begin{quote}
Yet I have found that these senses sometimes deceive me, and it is a matter of prudence never to confide completely in those who have deceived us even once...I am forced, finally, to concede that of the things which I once held to be true there is none that it would not be [rationally] permitted to doubt...And therefore I am forced to concede that from now on assent is accurately to be withheld from the same things too no less than from the overtly false ones, if I would want to find something certain. (\textit{First Meditation})
\end{quote}
We can restate \emph{Descartes' dream argument}, in the valid \textit{modus ponens} argument-form, as follows:
\begin{enumerate}
\item If what my senses tell me is sometimes wrong, then anything my senses tell me can be reasonably doubted. \hfill Premise
\item What my senses tell me is sometimes wrong [as in illusions, etc.]. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, anything my senses tell me can be reasonably doubted. \hfill 1, 2 MP
\item If anything my senses tell me can be reasonably doubted, then nothing my senses tell me is certain. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, nothing my senses tell me is certain. \hfill 3, 4 MP
\end{enumerate}
This conclusion teeters towards a \textit{global skepticism}, on which there are no justified beliefs. Descartes escapes global skepticism through the subjective experiences that are most certain:
\begin{quote}
No, if I was persuading myself of something, then certainly \textit{I} was...Here I find: it is cogitations: this alone cannot be rent from me. \textit{I} am, \textit{I} exist; it is certain. But for how long? So long as I am cogitating, of course...But what, then, am I? A cogitating thing. What is that? A thing doubting, understanding, affirming, denying, willing, not willing, also imagining, of course. (\textit{Second Meditation})
\end{quote}
Russell agrees with Descartes so far. But then Descartes infers that in all those subjective experiences, it is the same thing---the same \textit{I}---that undergoes those experiences:
\begin{quote}
What is there of these things that might be distinguished from my cogitation? What is there of these things that could be called ``separate" from me myself?...But truly \textit{I} am also the same one who imagines...\textit{I} am the same one who senses...I seem to see, I seem to hear, I seem to be warmed. (\textit{Second Meditation})
\end{quote}
Russell does not agree with Descartes' argument. We can restate the reasoning as follows:
\begin{enumerate}
\item If there is cogitation, then there is a thing that cogitates. \hfill Premise
\item There is cogitation [doubting, thinking, etc.]. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, there is a thing that cogitates. \hfill 1, 2 MP
\item The word `I' refers to a thing that cogitates on different occasions. \hfill Premise
\item If there is a thing that cogitates and the word `I' refers to it on different occasions, then a single self has one's cogitations. \hfill Premise
\item Thus, a single self has one's cogitations. \hfill 3\&4, 5 MP
\end{enumerate}
And (4) is support by different, seemingly correct uses of `I' to pick out the same entity. But Russell argues that (4) is not supported by the different, seemingly correct uses of `I':
\begin{quote}
When I look at my table and see a certain brown colour, what is quite certain at once is not `\textit{I} am seeing a brown colour', but rather, `a brown colour is being seen'. This of course involves something (or somebody) which (or who) sees the brown colour; but it does not itself involve that more or less permanent person whom we call `I'. So far as immediate certainty goes, it might be that the something which sees the brown colour is quite momentary, and not the same as the something which has some different experience the next moment. (\pageref{self})
\end{quote}
Buddhists like Vasubandhu (400s CE) gave a similar argument some centuries before Russell:
%\par Notice also that this argument has \textit{two} inferences. It has an intermediate conclusion in (4) before the final conclusion in (5). A lot of philosophical arguments work that way.
\begin{quote}
It is known that the expression, ``self," refers to a continuum of aggregates and not to anything else because there is no direct perception or correct inference...to a self. Therefore, there is no self. (\textit{Refutation of the Theory of a Self}, \S1)
\end{quote}
Exploring these theories of self is a great paper topic! You can try to answer, `Is there a permanent self underlying my experiences?' and discuss some of these varying views.
\hypertarget{chapter-iii.-the-nature-of-matter}{%
\chapter{The Nature of Matter}\label{chapter-iii.-the-nature-of-matter}}
In the preceding chapter we agreed, though without being able to find
demonstrative reasons, that it is rational to believe that our
sense-data---for example, those which we regard as associated with my
table---are really signs of the existence of something independent of us
and our perceptions. That is to say, over and above the sensations of
colour, hardness, noise, and so on, which make up the appearance of the
table to me, I assume that there is something else, of which these
things are appearances. The colour ceases to exist if I shut my eyes,
the sensation of hardness ceases to exist if I remove my arm from
contact with the table, the sound ceases to exist if I cease to rap the
table with my knuckles. But I do not believe that when all these things
cease the table ceases. On the contrary, I believe that it is because
the table exists continuously that all these sense-data will reappear
when I open my eyes, replace my arm, and begin again to rap with my
knuckles. The question we have to consider in this chapter is: What is
the nature of this real table, which persists independently of my
perception of it?
To this question physical science gives an answer, somewhat incomplete
it is true, and in part still very hypothetical, but yet deserving of
respect so far as it goes. Physical science, more or less unconsciously,
has drifted into the view that all natural phenomena ought to be reduced
to motions. Light and heat and sound are all due to wave-motions, which
travel from the body emitting them to the person who sees light or feels
heat or hears sound. That which has the wave-motion is either aether or
`gross matter', but in either case is
what the philosopher would call matter. The only properties which
science assigns to it are position in space, and the power of motion
according to the laws of motion. Science does not deny that it
\emph{may} have other properties; but if so, such other properties are
not useful to the man of science, and in no way assist him in explaining
the phenomena.
It is sometimes said that `light \emph{is} a form of
wave-motion', but this is misleading, for the light which
we immediately see, which we know directly by means of our senses, is
\emph{not} a form of wave-motion, but something quite
different---something which we all know if we are not blind, though we
cannot describe it so as to convey our knowledge to a man who is blind.
A wave-motion, on the contrary, could quite well be described to a blind
man, since he can acquire a knowledge of space by the sense of touch;
and he can experience a wave-motion by a sea voyage almost as well as we
can. But this, which a blind man can understand, is not what we mean by
\emph{light}: we mean by \emph{light} just that which a blind man can
never understand, and which we can never describe to him.
Now this something, which all of us who are not blind know, is not,
according to science, really to be found in the outer world: it is
something caused by the action of certain waves upon the eyes and nerves
and brain of the person who sees the light. When it is said that light
\emph{is} waves, what is really meant is that waves are the physical
cause of our sensations of light. But light itself, the thing which
seeing people experience and blind people do not, is not supposed by
science to form any part of the world that is independent of us and our
senses. \label{light} And very similar remarks would apply to other kinds of
sensations.
It is not only colours and sounds and so on that are absent from the
scientific world of matter, but also \emph{space} as we get it through
sight or touch. It is essential to science that its matter should be in
\emph{a} space, but the space in which it is cannot be exactly the space
we see or feel. To begin with, space as we see it is not the same as
space as we get it by the sense of touch; it is only by experience in
infancy that we learn how to touch things we see, or how to get a sight
of things which we feel touching us. But the space of science is neutral
as between touch and sight; thus it cannot be either the space of touch
or the space of sight.
Again, different people see the same object as of different shapes,
according to their point of view. A circular coin, for example, though
we should always \emph{judge} it to be circular, will \emph{look} oval
unless we are straight in front of it. When we judge that it \emph{is}
circular, we are judging that it has a real shape which is not its
apparent shape, but belongs to it intrinsically apart from its
appearance. But this real shape, which is what concerns science, must be
in a real space, not the same as anybody's
\emph{apparent} space. The real space is public, the apparent space is
private to the percipient. In different people's
\emph{private} spaces the same object seems to have different shapes;
thus the real space, in which it has its real shape, must be different
from the private spaces. The space of science, therefore, though
\emph{connected} with the spaces we see and feel, is not identical with
them, and the manner of its connexion requires investigation.
We agreed provisionally that physical objects cannot be quite like our
sense-data, but may be regarded as \emph{causing} our sensations. These
physical objects are in the space of science, which we may call
`physical' space. It is important to
notice that, if our sensations are to be caused by physical objects,
there must be a physical space containing these objects and our
sense-organs and nerves and brain. We get a sensation of touch from an
object when we are in contact with it; that is to say, when some part of
our body occupies a place in physical space quite close to the space
occupied by the object. We see an object (roughly speaking) when no
opaque body is between the object and our eyes in physical space.
Similarly, we only hear or smell or taste an object when we are
sufficiently near to it, or when it touches the tongue, or has some
suitable position in physical space relatively to our body. We cannot
begin to state what different sensations we shall derive from a given
object under different circumstances unless we regard the object and our
body as both in one physical space, for it is mainly the relative
positions of the object and our body that determine what sensations we
shall derive from the object.
\label{private} Now our sense-data are situated in our private spaces, either the space
of sight or the space of touch or such vaguer spaces as other senses may
give us. \label{onespace} If, as science and common sense assume, there is one public
all-embracing physical space in which physical objects are, the relative
positions of physical objects in physical space must more or less
correspond to the relative positions of sense-data in our private
spaces. There is no difficulty in supposing this to be the case. \label{distance} If we
see on a road one house nearer to us than another, our other senses will
bear out the view that it is nearer; for example, it will be reached
sooner if we walk along the road. Other people will agree that the house
which looks nearer to us is nearer; the ordnance map will take the same
view; and thus everything points to a spatial relation between the
houses corresponding to the relation between the sense-data which we see
when we look at the houses. Thus we may assume that there is a physical
space in which physical objects have spatial relations corresponding to
those which the corresponding sense-data have in our private spaces. It
is this physical space which is dealt with in geometry and assumed in
physics and astronomy.
Assuming that there is physical space, and that it does thus correspond
to private spaces, what can we know about it? We can know \emph{only}
what is required in order to secure the correspondence. That is to say,
we can know nothing of what it is like in itself, but we can know the
sort of arrangement of physical objects which results from their spatial
relations. We can know, for example, that the earth and moon and sun are
in one straight line during an eclipse, though we cannot know what a
physical straight line is in itself, as we know the look of a straight
line in our visual space. Thus we come to know much more about the
\emph{relations} of distances in physical space than about the distances
themselves; we may know that one distance is greater than another, or
that it is along the same straight line as the other, but we cannot have
that immediate acquaintance with physical distances that we have with
distances in our private spaces, or with colours or sounds or other
sense-data. We can know all those things about physical space which a
man born blind might know through other people about the space of sight;
but the kind of things which a man born blind could never know about the
space of sight we also cannot know about physical space. We can know the
properties of the relations required to preserve the correspondence with
sense-data, but we cannot know the nature of the terms between which the
relations hold.
\label{timeorder} With regard to time, our \emph{feeling} of duration or of the lapse of
time is notoriously an unsafe guide as to the time that has elapsed by
the clock. Times when we are bored or suffering pain pass slowly, times
when we are agreeably occupied pass quickly, and times when we are
sleeping pass almost as if they did not exist. Thus, in so far as time
is constituted by duration, there is the same necessity for
distinguishing a public and a private time as there was in the case of
space. But in so far as time consists in an \emph{order} of before and
after, there is no need to make such a distinction; the time-order which
events seem to have is, so far as we can see, the same as the time-order
which they do have. At any rate no reason can be given for supposing
that the two orders are not the same. The same is usually true of space:
if a regiment of men are marching along a road, the shape of the
regiment will look different from different points of view, but the men
will appear arranged in the same order from all points of view. Hence we
regard the order as true also in physical space, whereas the shape is
only supposed to correspond to the physical space so far as is required
for the preservation of the order.
In saying that the time-order which events seem to have is the same as
the time-order which they really have, it is necessary to guard against
a possible misunderstanding. It must not be supposed that the various
states of different physical objects have the same time-order as the
sense-data which constitute the perceptions of those objects. \label{thunder} Considered
as physical objects, the thunder and lightning are simultaneous; that is
to say, the lightning is simultaneous with the disturbance of the air in
the place where the disturbance begins, namely, where the lightning is.
But the sense-datum which we call hearing the thunder does not take
place until the disturbance of the air has travelled as far as to where
we are. Similarly, it takes about eight minutes for the
sun's light to reach us; thus, when we see the sun we
are seeing the sun of eight minutes ago. So far as our sense-data afford
evidence as to the physical sun they afford evidence as to the physical
sun of eight minutes ago; if the physical sun had ceased to exist within
the last eight minutes, that would make no difference to the sense-data
which we call `seeing the sun'. This
affords a fresh illustration of the necessity of distinguishing between
sense-data and physical objects.
What we have found as regards space is much the same as what we find in
relation to the correspondence of the sense-data with their physical
counterparts. \label{similarity} If one object looks blue and another red, we may
reasonably presume that there is some corresponding difference between
the physical objects; if two objects both look blue, we may presume a
corresponding similarity. But we cannot hope to be acquainted directly
with the quality in the physical object which makes it look blue or red.
Science tells us that this quality is a certain sort of wave-motion, and
this sounds familiar, because we think of wave-motions in the space we
see. But the wave-motions must really be in physical space, with which
we have no direct acquaintance; thus the real wave-motions have not that
familiarity which we might have supposed them to have. And what holds
for colours is closely similar to what holds for other sense-data. \label{relations} Thus
we find that, although the \emph{relations} of physical objects have all
sorts of knowable properties, derived from their correspondence with the
relations of sense-data, the physical objects themselves remain unknown
in their intrinsic nature, so far at least as can be discovered by means
of the senses. The question remains whether there is any other method of
discovering the intrinsic nature of physical objects.