-
Notifications
You must be signed in to change notification settings - Fork 4
/
06A99-Residuated.tex
102 lines (87 loc) · 5.87 KB
/
06A99-Residuated.tex
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
\documentclass[12pt]{article}
\usepackage{pmmeta}
\pmcanonicalname{Residuated}
\pmcreated{2013-03-22 18:53:22}
\pmmodified{2013-03-22 18:53:22}
\pmowner{CWoo}{3771}
\pmmodifier{CWoo}{3771}
\pmtitle{residuated}
\pmrecord{12}{41737}
\pmprivacy{1}
\pmauthor{CWoo}{3771}
\pmtype{Definition}
\pmcomment{trigger rebuild}
\pmclassification{msc}{06A99}
\pmclassification{msc}{06A15}
\pmdefines{residual}
\endmetadata
\usepackage{amssymb,amscd}
\usepackage{amsmath}
\usepackage{amsfonts}
\usepackage{mathrsfs}
% used for TeXing text within eps files
%\usepackage{psfrag}
% need this for including graphics (\includegraphics)
%\usepackage{graphicx}
% for neatly defining theorems and propositions
\usepackage{amsthm}
% making logically defined graphics
%%\usepackage{xypic}
\usepackage{pst-plot}
% define commands here
\newcommand*{\abs}[1]{\left\lvert #1\right\rvert}
\newtheorem{prop}{Proposition}
\newtheorem{thm}{Theorem}
\newtheorem{ex}{Example}
\newcommand{\real}{\mathbb{R}}
\newcommand{\pdiff}[2]{\frac{\partial #1}{\partial #2}}
\newcommand{\mpdiff}[3]{\frac{\partial^#1 #2}{\partial #3^#1}}
\newcommand{\down}{\downarrow\!\!}
\begin{document}
Let $P,Q$ be two posets. Recall that a function $f:P\to Q$ is order preserving iff $x\le y$ implies $f(x)\le f(y)$. This is equivalent to saying that the preimage of any down set under $f$ is a down set.
\textbf{Definition} A function $f:P\to Q$ between ordered sets $P,Q$ is said to be \emph{residuated} if the preimage of any principal down set is a principal down set. In other words, for any $y\in Q$, there is some $x\in P$ such that $$f^{-1}(\down{y}) = \down{x},$$ where $f^{-1}(A)$ for any $A\subseteq Q$ is the set $\lbrace a\in X\mid f(a)\in A\rbrace$, and $\down b = \lbrace c \mid c\le b\rbrace$.
Let us make some observations on a residuated function $f:P\to Q$:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $f$ is order preserving.
\begin{proof}
Suppose $a\le b$ in $P$. Then there is some $c\in P$ such that $\down c = f^{-1}(\down f(b))$. Since $f(b) \in \down f(b)$, $b \in \down c$, or $b\le c$, which means $a\le c$, or $a\in \down c$. But this implies $a\in f^{-1}(\down f(b))$, so that $f(a) \in \down f(b)$, or $f(a)\le f(b)$.
\end{proof}
\item The $x$ in the definition above is unique.
\begin{proof} If $\down x = \down z$, then $x\in \down z$, or $x\le z$. Similarly, $z\le x$, so that $x=z$.
\end{proof}
\item $g:Q\to P$ given by $g(y)=x$ is a well-defined function, with the following properties:
\begin{enumerate}
\item $g$ is order preserving,
\item $1_P \le g\circ f$,
\item $f\circ g\le 1_Q$.
\end{enumerate}
\begin{proof}
$g$ is order preserving: if $r\le s$ in $Q$, then $\down r \subseteq \down s$, so that $\down u = f^{-1}(\down r)\subseteq f^{-1}(\down s) = \down v$, where $u=g(r)$ and $v=g(s)$. But $\down u\subseteq \down v$ implies $u\le v$, or $g(r)\le g(s)$.
$1_P \le g\circ f$: let $x\in P$, $y=f(x)$, and $z=g(y)$. Then $x\in f^{-1}(y) \subseteq f^{-1}(\down y) = \down z$, which implies $x\le z=g(f(x))$ as desired.
$f\circ g\le 1_Q$: pick $y\in Q$ and let $x=g(y)$. Then $f^{-1}(\down y)=\down x$, so that $f(x)\in f(\down x) = f(f^{-1}( \down y))=\down y$, or $f(x)\le y$, or $f(g(y))=f(x) \le y$ as a result.
\end{proof}
\end{enumerate}
Actually, the third observation above characterizes $f$ being residuated:
\begin{prop} If $f$ is order preserving, and $g$ satisfies $3(a)$ through $3(c)$, then $f$ is residuated. In fact, such a $g$ is unique.
\end{prop}
\begin{proof}
Suppose $y\in Q$, and let $x=g(y)$. We want to show that $\down x=f^{-1}(\down y)$. First, suppose $a \in f^{-1}(\down y)$. Then $f(a) \le y$, which means $g(f(a))\le g(y)=x$. But then $a\le g(f(a))$, and we get $a\le x$, or $a\in \down x$. Next, suppose $a\le x=g(y)$. Then $f(a) \le f(x) =f(g(y))\le y$, so $a\in f^{-1}(f(a))\subseteq f^{-1}(\down y)$.
To see uniqueness, suppose $h:Q\to P$ is order preserving such that $1_P \le h\circ f$ and $f\circ h\le 1_Q$. Then $g = 1_P \circ g \le (h \circ f )\circ g = h \circ (f\circ g) \le = h\circ 1_Q = h$ and $h = 1_P \circ h \le (g\circ f) \circ h = g \circ (f \circ h) \le g \circ 1_Q = g$.
\end{proof}
\textbf{Definition}. Given a residuated function $f:P\to Q$, the unique function $g:Q\to P$ defined above is called the \emph{residual} of $f$, and is denoted by $f^+$.
For example, given any function $f: A\to B$, the induced function $f: P(A)\to P(B)$ (by abuse of notation, we use the same notation as original function $f$), given by $f(S)=\lbrace f(a)\mid a\in S\rbrace$ is residuated. Its residual is the function $f^{-1}: P(B)\to P(A)$, given by $f^{-1}(T)=\lbrace a \in A\mid f(a)\in T\rbrace$.
Here are some properties of residuated functions and their residuals:
\begin{itemize}
\item A bijective residuated function is an order isomorphism, and conversely. Furthermore, the residual is residuated, and is its inverse.
\item If $f: P\to Q$ is residuated, then $f\circ f^+ \circ f = f$ and $f^+ \circ f \circ f^+ = f^+$.
\item If $f: P\to Q$ and $g:Q\to R$ are residuated, so is $g\circ f$ and $(g\circ f)^+=f^+\circ g^+$.
\item If $f: P\to Q$ is residuated, then $f^+\circ f: P \to P$ is a closure map on $P$. Conversely, any closure function can be decomposed as the functional composition of a residuated function and its residual.
\end{itemize}
\textbf{Remark}. Residuated functions and their residuals are closely related to Galois connections. If $f:P\to Q$ is residuated, then $(f,f^+)$ forms a Galois connection between $P$ and $Q$. On the other hand, if $(f,g)$ is a Galois connection between $P$ and $Q$, then $f: P\to Q$ is residuated, and $g: Q\to P$ is $f^+$. Note that PM defines a Galois connection as a pair of order-preserving maps, where as in Blyth, they are order reversing.
\begin{thebibliography}{6}
\bibitem{tsb} T.S. Blyth, {\em Lattices and Ordered Algebraic Structures}, Springer, New York (2005).
\bibitem{gg} G. Gr\"atzer, {\it General Lattice Theory}, 2nd Edition, Birkh\"auser (1998)
\end{thebibliography}
%%%%%
%%%%%
\end{document}